Whether a Pope can be Deposed by the Church, even as he is Elected by her; and in what Cases?
It
cannot be held that the pope, by the very fact of being a heretic, would cease
to be pope antecedently [prior] to a declaration of the Church. It is true that some seem to hold this
position; but we will discuss this in the next article. What is truly a matter of debate, is whether
the pope, after he is declared by the Church to be a heretic, is deposed ipso
facto by Christ the Lord, or if the Church ought to depose him. In any case, as long as the Church has not
issued a juridical declaration, he must always be considered the pope, as we
will make more clear in the next article. ... [1]
I
suppose that the Pope can lose the papacy in three ways. Firstly, through natural death; secondly,
through voluntary abdication; thirdly, through deposition. (…) On this third
way of losing the papacy, many difficulties call for our consideration; but
that we may be brief in our treatment we will reduce all the difficulties to two
principal headings: namely, in what cases deposition is possible, and by what
power it ought to be accomplished. And,
to address the first question, there are three principal cases in which the
deposition of a Pope can occur. The
first is the case of heresy or infidelity; the second, that of perpetual
insanity; the third, that of doubt concerning the validity of an election.
Concerning
the case of heresy, theologians and jurists dispute over many things, and our
work does not permit us to discuss all of them in great detail; but all the
doctors agree that the Pope can be deposed for heresy, and we shall cite them
when we treat of the difficulties. We
have an explicit text in the chapter Si papa, distinction 40, where it
is said: “No mortal man presumes to rebuke the Pope for his faults, because he
who is to judge all men is judged by no one, unless he be found to have
deviated from the faith.” This exception
manifestly signifies that a judicial sentence should be passed against the Pope
in the case of heresy. The same is
confirmed by the letter of [Pope] Adrian II, related in the eighth general
Synod, session VII, in which he says that the Roman Pontiff is judged by no
one; but, [he adds,] an anathema was pronounced against [Pope] Honorius by the
[bishops of] the East because he had been accused of heresy, which alone makes
it licit for inferiors to resist the doings of their superiors. Similarly, even Pope St. Clement says in his
first epistle that St. Peter taught that a heretical Pope should be deposed.
["Neither does
Christ wish to ordain you a judge or arbiter of worldly affairs (said St. Peter to Clement), lest,
overwhelmed by the temporal concerns of men, you be unable to devote time to
the Word of God and discern good men from bad according to the rule of truth. (…) For if you be occupied with worldly
affairs, you will deceive both yourself and those who hear you, since you will
be incapable adequately to distinguishing for either the things that pertain to
his salvation; and thence it will come to pass also that you, as one who has
not taught what pertains to men’s salvation, will be deposed (deponaris)
and your disciples will perish through their ignorance." (First Epistle of Clement to
James. Decretales Pseudo-Isadorianae et Capitula Angilramni, Paulus
Hinschius, Ex Officina Bernhardi Tauchnitz, Lipsiae, 1863, p. 32.)]
The
reason for this is the following: we are obliged to separate ourselves from
heretics, according to 1 Tim. 3: “A heretic, after the first and second
admonition, avoid.” But he who remains
in the Pontificate should not be avoided; on the contrary, the Church is
obliged to be united to him and to be in communion with him, since he is her
supreme head; therefore, if the Pope is a heretic, either the Church is obliged
to remain in communion with him, or else he ought to be deposed from the
papacy. The first hypothesis—that the
Church is obliged to follow a heretical head—is evidently destructive to the
Church and of its very nature involves the danger that the whole ecclesiastical
government would fall into error; on the other hand, since the heretic is an
enemy of the Church, the Church has a natural right to take action against such
a Pope, because she has the right to self-defense against her enemies, and a
heretical Pope is an enemy; consequently, she has the right to take action
against him. By all means, then, the
second option should be taken, and such a Pope should be deposed.
But
you will object, saying that Christ our Lord allowed unbelieving and heretical
men to remain in the chair of Moses, such as the Pharisees were; “The Scribes
and Pharisees have sat upon the chair of Moses; therefore, observe and do
whatever they tell you” (Mt. 23). St.
Jerome, in his commentary on the eighth chapter of Isaias, writes that the
Pharisees were heretics and held perverse dogmas in accordance with various superstitions
and traditions; and their errors have been enumerated by Epiphanius (in
Panario, libro 1, cap. 16), Josephus (de bello Judaico lib. 2, cap. 7 ad
finem), and Baronius (in apparatu annalium, cap. 7). Therefore, even a heretic and an unbeliever should
be allowed to remain upon the chair of Peter—for he cannot [solemnly] define
his heresy or error [as a dogma of faith, for Papal infallibility would prevent
this], and thus the Church will always remain free from heresy.
I
respond that Christ our Lord did not command that the Pharisees be permitted to
remain on the chair of Moses even in the case that they should be declared as
heretics, but only on condition that they are still tolerated; and this applies
to any heretic or unbeliever who is in the priesthood or episcopacy. If they have not yet been declared [as
heretics] and deposed from their position of authority, the faithful ought to
listen to them and obey them, because they still retain their power and jurisdiction;
but not if the Church should decide to tolerate them no longer, and declares them
to be heretics, which Christ our Lord does not prohibit in the words cited
above.
But
the question arises whether the Pope can be deposed in any case of heresy, and
in whatever way he may be a heretic, or if certain conditions are required,
without which heresy alone is not sufficient to depose the Pope. I respond that the Pope cannot be deposed or
lose the papacy unless two conditions are simultaneously met: namely, that the
heresy be public and juridically notorious, not occult; and that he be
incorrigible and pertinacious in his heresy.
When these two conditions are met the Pope can be deposed, but he cannot
be deposed without them; and, on the other hand, even if he is not an infidel
in his heart, but exteriorly he behaves like a heretic, he can be deposed, and
the sentence of deposition will be valid.
Now,
concerning the first condition, even among Catholic authors there are some who
disagree, thinking that the Pope loses his papal jurisdiction even for occult
heresy, since jurisdiction is founded on the true faith and its orthodox
profession; and we can cite the following authors as supporting this latter
opinion:
Turrecremata
(lib. 4, 2 p. a capite 18, et lib. 2, cap. 102), Paludanus (in opusculo de hac
re), Castro (lib. 2 de justa haereticorum punitione, cap. 22 et 23), Simancas
(de catholicis institutionibus, cap. 21), Driedo (de libertate Christiana, cap.
16), and others.
And
some authors defend this position so absolutely that they think the Pope would
fall from the papacy even because of a [purely] mental heresy; and their
reasoning is that, in order to be Pope, it is required as a necessary condition
that he be a member of the Church—for as Pope he is her supreme head—and that
he be joined to the rock upon which the Church is founded, that is, the faith
and the confession of Peter. For, even
as the Church cannot be without interior faith, neither can the papacy, since
it is founded upon the same profession [of faith] as the Church is; and it was
for this reason that Christ asked for this profession of faith from Peter
before He promised him the papacy. And
Azorius (as cited above in chapter 7) attributes this opinion to Turrecremata
and Castro.
Others
think that it is necessary for the heresy to be external, and externally
proved (externe probata), for the Pope to be deposed from the papacy; and the authors who hold
this opinion are the following:
Soto
(in 4, dist. 22, quaest. 2, art. 2), Cano (lib. 4 de locis, capite ultimo ad
duodecim—he does not even concede any probability to the opposite opinion),
Cajetan (de auctoritate papae, cap. 18 et 19), Suarez, Azorius, and Bellarmine
(lib. 2 de Romano pontifice, cap. 30).
The
foundation for this opinion [of Bellarmine's opinion] is that occult heretics, as long as they are not
condemned by the Church and cut off from her, remain parts of the Church, and
are in communion with her exteriorly, although they do not share in her
interior spirit; even the Pope, therefore, is not cut off from the Church by
the fact that he is an occult heretic; consequently, he can still be her head,
even as he is still a part and a member, although not a living one.
This
opinion is confirmed by the fact that lesser priests can exercise acts of [the powers of] Order and ecclesiastical jurisdiction;
for a heretical priest can confect the Sacraments and give absolution in
extreme necessity; therefore, not even faith is required for the Pope to
exercise his jurisdiction, as long as he has not been deposed by the Church;
and this is especially true in his case, because [as Pope] he is not capable of
incurring excommunication for being a heretic, as inferiors can.
Finally,
if the Pope, by the very fact of being an occult heretic, fell from the Papacy
even before the Church becomes aware of it and judges him, it would follow as a
consequence that, if he speedily came back to his senses by sincere repentance,
he could no longer exercise the functions of the papacy, since he has lost that
dignity, which is not restored by God through Penance as grace is. But if he cannot act as Pope he will be
obliged to renounce the papacy, which is certainly a very grave inconvenience;
for he will be obliged to betray himself; for it will be necessary to publicize
the reason for his renunciation, or at least to consult others about the
matter. Moreover, many other problems
would follow if, by the very fact that he is an occult heretic, the Pope would
lose the papacy; for everything would become perplexing, and the door would be
opened to schism, if without considering the judgment of the Church he were to
lose the papacy for an offence known perhaps to him alone.
This
reasoning removes the foundation from the other opinion, since, in order for
someone to be Pope, it is required only that he be a member of the Church by
exterior communication, at least in the way that someone is said to be
sufficiently a member of the Church in order to govern her externally (for it
is in this sense that the Pope is head of the Church), even if he does not
participate in her interior spirit by reason of an occult heresy or sin; and it
suffices for him to be united to the rock and to the Church in this way, that
is, by exterior communication; for he is considered by the Church as joined to
her as long as he has not been cut off by her or declared to be a heretic.
As
to the other argument adduced—namely, that the Church cannot remain the true
Church without interior faith—I respond that [if that were true] it could be
proved in the same way that the Pope cannot retain the papacy without grace,
and that he loses it by the very fact of falling into mortal sin—which was a
heresy of Wycliff, condemned among his articles in the Council of Constance—because,
even as the Church (taken generally) cannot exist without interior faith, so
neither can it exist without charity.
The
authority of the papacy, therefore, is not founded upon the personal faith of
any individual, inasmuch as any one person can express it according to his own
understanding; rather, it is founded upon the common faith of the whole Church—and
the fact that the Pope cannot fail in this faith [Luke 22:31-32] means that, even if he were
personally a heretic, yet insofar as he teaches ex cathedra he cannot
teach anything contrary to the faith. It
is in this faith, therefore—which is the faith of the papacy, and not of
the person; and which was the faith of Peter and his confession—in this alone
the papacy is founded, and not in the personal faith even of the very person of
the Pope.
Now,
since the Church by definition is the congregation of all the faithful, it is
incompatible with her nature for all of her members to without the true faith
of God, even mental, in the same way that it is impossible for all the faithful
to be without grace.
The
second condition for the Pope to be deposed—namely, that he be incorrigible and
contumacious in his heresy—is evident; for, if he is ready to be corrected, and not pertinacious in his heresy, he is not considered to be a heretic, as we gather
from the chapter Dixit Apostolus 24, q. 3; therefore, if the Pope is
ready to be corrected, he should not be deposed as a heretic. It is also evident from the fact that the
Apostle commands that the heretic be avoided only after a first and second
admonition; consequently, if after being admonished he returns to his senses,
he is not to be avoided. Since, then, it
is because of that very precept of the Apostle that a Pope ought to be deposed
for heresy, it follows from the same precept that, if he can be corrected, he
is not to be deposed. And indeed, since
the Pope, before he is deposed, ought to be urged to return to his right mind,
plainly if he corrects himself after being admonished it does not seem possible
to proceed further by deposing him.
It
is of some help to consider the case of Pope Marcellinus as described in the
chapter Nunc autem of the 21st distinction (which we have
already address in the preceding disputation).
For, although he was declared to be an infidel by a Council of bishops;
nevertheless, because he returned to his senses and was willingly corrected, he
remained in the papacy, and as Pope he later died for the faith; therefore,
unless a Pope abide pertinaciously and incorrigibly in his heresy, he should
not be deposed from the papacy. See the
gloss by Huguccio on the chapter Si Papa, distinction 40 (cited above),
where he holds the same opinion and declares that, if a Pope falls into heresy
and, after being corrected, lapses once again, he can be corrected a second
time; but after two corrections, if he falls into heresy once more, he is not
to be admitted back, even if he shows himself ready to be corrected, but is
rather to be considered incorrigible and deposed; and Cajetan, in his Opusculum
de auctoritate papae, ch. 22, provides a good foundation for this with the
saying of the Apostle: “After the first and second correction avoid [him],
knowing that such a one is subversive.” When,
therefore, the first and second corrections have been given, and he falls once
more into heresy, he is considered to be incorrigible according to human
judgment; and so, lest the corrections be iterated without end, they are
terminated with the second one, and after this he is held to be incorrigible. (…)
The
second case of the deposition of a Pope is that of perpetual insanity. (…)
The
third case of the deposition of a Pope is where there is doubt as to the
validity of a papal election; and under this heading we include all those
instances in which the Church cannot free herself from doubt and become certain
of who is her head; for, because the election of Popes has been committed to
her, she has the right to have certainty about the one who is elected to be
Pope and her universal head. (…) In every case in which there is doubt as to
who is true Pope, or as to the election, it pertains to the Church to judge the
matter, not because she is superior to the Pope (even if he be Pope in
reality), but because she is superior to the election of the Pope and
all the doubts that can arise from it; and [this means that] she is superior per
accidens to the one who is, in reality, a real Pope.
But
you will object: What if the Church [deems] someone not to be a true Pope who in
reality and in the sight of God really is the Pope, although others are in
doubt about it? For, in that case, he
has already received supreme power over the Church from Christ our Lord, for he
has it from his election, which was valid in itself [even if it was not so in
the estimation of others]. Hence, even
if the Church [putatively] deposes him, she will not be able to take away the
power given him by Christ our Lord, for this cannot be lost without the fault
of the one elected. In such a case, if
the Church proceeds to elect another Pope, there will then be two persons in
the Church who really and in the sight of God have supreme power over the
Church—which is impossible, since by the institution of Christ our Lord there
ought to be only one supreme pastor; therefore, it is impossible that this
supreme power would really be given to two persons because of the action of the
Church.
I
respond that there is no doubt that the Church can judge and depose a Pope who
is innocent in reality, but proven to be harmful, just as, if he were not a
heretic in reality [see Bellarmine's commentary on Liberius], but nevertheless were juridically proven to be a heretic
exteriorly, he could be held not to be the Pope. For even as, when he is truly at fault, he does not lose the papacy when he committed the fault, yet has not been judged by the
Church, but rather when the Church declares him to have committed it; so also,
even if he is not at fault in reality, nevertheless, if he is guilty according
to the declaration of the Church (because it has been juridically proven so),
he still loses the papacy. For this is
expedient for the governing of the Church, which is done in a human manner and
with human proofs, and which requires only juridical truth, not mathematical; and,
because the papacy does not consist in a character [i.e. of Orders] which cannot be destroyed
by any action, but rather in jurisdiction, which can depend upon moral
conditions; therefore, the power of the papacy can depend upon the moral and
juridical notoriety of a fault as a condition [for the loss of its possession],
even though [the possessor] be innocent in reality.
Nevertheless,
I add that it seems more likely that such a case—namely, that the Church should
judge someone not to be Pope who really is Pope in reality—is impossible; for
this would mean that the universal Church erred on a matter that is extremely
serious and affects the whole body of the Church; so that, even as the Church
cannot err in judging to canonize a saint, so also it seems impossible that the
Church would err in condemning someone as a heretic and deposing him from the
papacy; nor would God permit her to judge that one who in fact is really Pope
is not the Pope.
But
you will ask if we should admit of any case, besides those already given, in
which the Pope should be deposed. I
respond in the negative; any case that can be imagined is reduced to one of
these three, and he can be deposed for no other. This is the common opinion of theologians,
and also of many jurists. (…) The reason for this is, first of all, that in law
there is no crime for which the Pope can be deposed except heresy. (…) The
second and even stronger reason is that, according to law, the Pope is judged
by no one (…); therefore the deposition of a Pope cannot be done directly, by
way of judgment and punishment, since the Pope has no superior on earth by whom
he could be punished or corrected. He
can be deposed, then, only because on his side there is an incompatibility with
being head of the Church; namely, because he is separated and segregated from
her by leaving the faith, in such wise that the Church has the obligation to
avoid him; whereas for other sins (no matter how grave) the Church is never
obliged to avoid him, because he is not segregated from her—nor can he be
separated from her by excommunication—and therefore he should not be forced out
from the papacy; for, if he were forced out of it, the reason would not be that
the Church cannot adhere and remain united to him, but rather that she repels
the Pope from the papacy as being unworthy of it due to his demerits; but this
latter cannot be done except by someone having authority and jurisdiction over
the guilty one who is being punished for his demerits; and since this power is
found in no man, not even in the Church (since the Pope cannot have any
superior on earth), consequently he cannot be judged for such crimes. Neither is the Pope directly judged for
heresy; but, because Scripture and Divine Law oblige the Church to separate
herself from a heretic and not to communicate with him, therefore, once she has
declared that he is a heretic, the Church cannot regard him as her head; for
she cannot communicate with him; but the head to which the body is not united
and with which it does not communicate is no head at all [Note: JST and Cajetan believe an additional step is required for the pope to fall from the Pontificate].
And
with this explanation we can dispel the reasons that move some canonists to
hold the opposite opinion. (…) These think that a Pope can be deposed for
simony and other crimes that threaten to cause great harm and scandal to the
Church; for, even as the heresy of a Pope can seriously threaten the Church, so
also can other crimes, by which he might destroy her government and treat her
with violence in the manner of a tyrant; but by Natural Law the Church can
defend herself and repel him by force; but this is impossible unless she depose
him, even as she deposes him for the crime of heresy; and she would be doing it
for the same reasons. (…) Nevertheless, what we have already established sets
these arguments at naught; for, even if it is true that a criminal Pope is very
detrimental to the Church, nevertheless, the Church is neither obliged nor able
to separate herself from his communion; nor can she punish him judicially; and
therefore she ought to sustain him as her head.
But in the case of heresy she is obliged to separate herself from him,
as was said; and because of his heresy she should not regard him as her
head. But [in the case of other crimes]
she can still defend herself, not indeed by deposing him, but by repelling him
with force if he proceeds against her with tyrannical violence; and if he
wishes to take up arms in order to perpetrate something contrary to justice,
she can take up arms to repel him; and, similarly, if he decrees something
contrary to good morals he is not to be obeyed, for an unjust law has no
binding force [Bellarmine teaches the same. See: De Romano Pontifice, lib. iv, cap. xv; lib. ii, cap. xix; On Councils, lib. ii, cap. viii, & xix)]. (…)
But
another difficulty remains to be discussed: namely, by what power this
deposition of the Pope should be accomplished.
And the whole question turns around two points. The first is the declaratory sentence by which
the crime of the Pope is declared. Who
should issue it, the Cardinals or a general Council? And if a general Council, by whose authority
should it be summoned, and who has the power to decide such a case? The second point is the deposition itself, which
is to be done after a sentence has been passed declaring the crime. Is it done by the power of the Church, or is
it done by Christ our Lord himself without any intermediary as soon as the
declaration has been made?
To
address the first point: we should say that this handling of the deposition of
a Pope, as regards the declaration of the crime, pertains in no way to the
Cardinals, but to a general Council.
This is evident, first of all, from the practice of the Church; for in
the case of [Pope] Marcellinus, who offered incense to idols, a Synod was
convoked to discuss his cause, as we gather from the chapter Nunc autem,
distinction 21. And in the case of the
schism in which there were three putative Popes claiming obedience the Synod of
Constance was gathered to sedate the schism.
Also, in the case of Pope Symmachus, the Council of Rome was gathered to
discuss the accusations that had been made against him, as Antonius Augustinus
relates in his treatise on law (epitome juris de pontifice maximo, titulo 13);
and the canons cited above testify that the Popes who wished to purge
themselves of certain charges brought against them did so in the presence of
Councils. Secondly, it is also certain
that the power to handle the causes of Popes, as well as those things that
pertain to their deposition, has never been entrusted to the Cardinals; hence,
it remains in the deposit of the Church, whose authority is represented by a
general Council; for only the election of Popes has been committed to the
Cardinals, and nothing more, as can be ascertained by reading the citations
from canon law that we have provided in the first article [of this
disputation]. (…)
But
we have yet to explain by whose authority this Council should be convoked; for
it cannot be done by the authority of the Pope, since it is gathered in
opposition to him; but no Council can be legitimate unless it is convoked by
the authority of the Pope; hence, the Pope can deny any Council its right to
convoke, and can nullify it, if it is gathered against his will—especially
since, before the declaration of his crime, he still has the power of Pope;
therefore, any Council that is gathered is subject to his power, and
consequently he can dissolve it if he wishes.
I
respond that such a Council can be convoked by the authority of the Church,
which is in the bishops, or the greater part of them; for by Divine Law the
Church has the right to segregate herself from a heretical Pope, and
consequently she has the right to apply all the means that of their very nature
are necessary for this segregation; but one such means, which is necessary of
its very nature, is that she acquire juridical certainty about the crime; but
the crime cannot be juridically certified unless she form a competent judgment;
and in so grave a matter a competent judgment cannot be issued by any except a
general Council, for we are dealing with the universal head of the Church,
wherefore the matter belongs to the judgment of the universal Church, which is
had in a general Council. And therefore
I do not agree with Fr. Suarez, who thinks that this matter could be handled by
provincial Councils; for a provincial Council does not represent the universal
Church, and therefore it does not have the authority of the universal Church,
in order to be able to decide the matter; and even if many provincial Councils
were gathered they would neither represent the universal Church nor have her
authority.
But
if we speak, not of the authority by which the judgment is rendered, but of
that by which the Council is convoked, I do not think that its convocation has
been entrusted to anyone in a determinate manner; but I think that it could be
done either by the Cardinals, who would be able to give the bishops knowledge
of what is going on; or else the bishops who are nearer [geographically to the
Pope] could denounce the matter to the others, so that all would come; or
again, it could even happen at the insistence of the [Catholic] princes—in
which case the summons would not, indeed, have any coercive force, as it has when
the Pope convokes a Council; rather, it would be denunciative in nature,
notifying the bishops of the [alleged] crime and making it manifest that they
should come to remedy the situation.
The
Pope, therefore, cannot annul such a Council, since he himself is a part [of
the Church], and the Church by Divine Law has the power to gather a Council for
this end, because she has the right to segregate herself from a heretic.
However,
concerning the second point—namely, by whose authority the declaration and deposition
are to be accomplished—there is disagreement among theologians, for it is not
apparent who should effect the deposition, since it is an act of judgment and
jurisdiction, and no one can exercise these in relation to the Pope. Cajetan (in opusculo de potestate papae,
capite 20) relates two explanations that are extreme opposites, and two others
that are in the middle. One of the
extremes is that the Pope, by the very fact [ipso facto] that he is a
heretic, is deposed without any human judgment.
The other extreme is that there is a power that is superior to the Pope
without any qualification, and this power is able to judge him. Of the two intermediate opinions, the one
holds that the pope does not recognize anyone as superior absolutely, but only
in the case of heresy. The other holds
that there is no power on earth that is superior to the Pope, whether
absolutely or in the case of heresy; but there is a ministerial
power.
Even
as the Church has a ministerial power in the election of a Pope—not as to the
conferring of power, since this is done immediately by Christ, as we have said
in the first article; but in the designation of the person—so, too, in the
deposition (which is the destruction of the bond by which the papacy is joined
to this particular person) the Church has a ministerial power and deposes the
Pope ministerially, while it is Christ who deprives him of the papacy authoritatively.
Of
these two [intermediate] explanations, Azorius (2, tom. 2, cap. 7) adopts the
first, which holds that the Church is superior to the Pope in the case of
heresy; while Cajetan adopts the latter and treats of it at length. Bellarmine, however, reports his opinion and
attacks it in his work de Romano pontifice, bk. 2, ch. 30, objecting
especially to these two points: namely, that Cajetan says that the Pope who is
a manifest heretic [according to the Church's human judgment] is not ipso facto deposed; and also that the Church
deposes the Pope in a real and authoritative manner. Suarez also, in the disputation that we have
frequently cited, sect. 6, num. 7, attacks Cajetan for saying that, in the case
of heresy, the Church is superior to the Pope, not insofar as he is Pope, but
insofar as he is a private individual.
Cajetan, however, did not say this; he only said that, even in the case
of heresy, the Church is not absolutely superior to the Pope, but instead is
superior to the bond between the papacy and the person, dissolving it in the
same way that she forged it at his election; and this power of the Church is ministerial,
for only Christ our Lord is superior to the Pope without qualification. Hence, Bellarmine and Suarez are of the
opinion that, by the very fact that the Pope is a manifest heretic and declared
to be incorrigible, he is deposed [ipso facto] by Christ our Lord without any intermediary,
and not by any authority of the Church.
The
opinion of Cajetan, then, is contained in these three propositions:
1) The first is that it is not precisely the fact of heresy, as such, that deprives a heretical Pope of the papacy and deposes him.
2) The second is that, even in the case of heresy, the Church has no power or superiority over the Pope in relation to his papal power (as if there were a power superior to that one, even in such a case), for the power of the Church is in no way superior to that of the Pope; and consequently her power is not superior to the Pope [himself] without qualification.
3) The third is that the power of the Church has as its object the application of the papal power to the person, both in designating that person [as Pope] by electing him, and also in separating this power from the same person by declaring that he is a heretic and must be avoided by the faithful [Vitandus]. For, although the declaration of the crime is like an antecedent disposition and is related in a ministerial way to the deposition itself; nevertheless, in a dispositive and ministerial way it [i.e., the declaration] attains even to the form, inasmuch as, by acting upon the disposition, it acts mediately upon the form; even as, in the generation or corruption of a man, the one who generates him does not produce or educe the form; nor does the one who corrupts a man destroy the form, but only the bond or separation of the form—and this is done by acting immediately upon the dispositions of the matter in relation to the form; and, with those dispositions as a medium, the agent’s activity reaches the form itself.
1) The first is that it is not precisely the fact of heresy, as such, that deprives a heretical Pope of the papacy and deposes him.
2) The second is that, even in the case of heresy, the Church has no power or superiority over the Pope in relation to his papal power (as if there were a power superior to that one, even in such a case), for the power of the Church is in no way superior to that of the Pope; and consequently her power is not superior to the Pope [himself] without qualification.
3) The third is that the power of the Church has as its object the application of the papal power to the person, both in designating that person [as Pope] by electing him, and also in separating this power from the same person by declaring that he is a heretic and must be avoided by the faithful [Vitandus]. For, although the declaration of the crime is like an antecedent disposition and is related in a ministerial way to the deposition itself; nevertheless, in a dispositive and ministerial way it [i.e., the declaration] attains even to the form, inasmuch as, by acting upon the disposition, it acts mediately upon the form; even as, in the generation or corruption of a man, the one who generates him does not produce or educe the form; nor does the one who corrupts a man destroy the form, but only the bond or separation of the form—and this is done by acting immediately upon the dispositions of the matter in relation to the form; and, with those dispositions as a medium, the agent’s activity reaches the form itself.
That
Cajetan’s first proposition is true is evident from what we have already said;
nor does Bellarmine attack it legitimately.
And the truth of it is certain, both because the Pope, no matter how
truly and publicly he be a heretic, cannot be deposed if he is ready to be
corrected, as we have said above; nor does Divine Law give the Church the power
to depose him, for she neither can nor ought to avoid him [until he be proven
incorrigible]; for the Apostle says, “Avoid a heretic after the first and
second admonition”; consequently, before he has been admonished a first and
second time, he is not to be avoided by the Church; neither, then, is he to be
deposed. So it is false to say that the
Pope is deposed by the very fact [ipso facto] that he is a public
heretic; for it is possible for him to be a public heretic while he has not yet
been admonished by the Church, nor declared to be incorrigible; and also
because, as Azorius notes well in the place referenced above, no bishop loses
his jurisdiction and episcopal power ipso facto, no matter how much of
an external heretic he may be, until the Church declares him such and deposes
him; and this is true despite the fact that he incurs excommunication ipso
facto; for only those who are excommunicated as non tolerati [i.e., vitandi]
lose their jurisdiction—which is to say, those who have been excommunicated by
name, or who are manifest strikers of the clergy; so, if no bishop (or any
other prelate) loses his power ipso facto solely from external heresy,
why would the Pope lose it before a declaration is given by the Church—especially
because the Pope cannot incur excommunication? For, as I presume, there is no
excommunication that is immediately incurred because of Divine Law; but the
Pope cannot be excommunicated by any human law, since he is above all human
law.
Cajetan’s
second proposition is proved from the fact that the power of the Pope, without
any qualification, is a power derived from Christ our Lord, and not from the
Church; and to that power Christ subjected the whole Church, that is, all the
faithful without any restriction—as is certain de fide, and has been
proven at length already; therefore, in no case can the Church have a power
superior to that of the pope—unless there is a case in which the Pope’s power
becomes dependent upon the Church and inferior to her; but, by the very fact
that it becomes inferior in such a case, it is already altered and is not the
same power as before—since beforehand it was superior to the whole Church and
independent of her, and yet in this [supposed] case becomes dependent and
inferior. It is never verified, then,
that the Church has a power that is formally superior to that of the Pope [this shows that neither John of St. Thomas nor Cajetan were Conciliarists]; for
it is necessary, in order for the Church to have, in some case, a power
superior to the Pope’s, that the Pope’s power be formally different from what
it had been previously, for [in such a hypothetical case] it is not full and
supreme in the way that it was before.
Nor does any authority give us certainty that Christ our Lord gave a
power to the Church in this way, so that her power would be superior to the
Pope’s; for the things that are said about the case of heresy do not indicate
any formal superiority over the power of the Pope, but only that the Church
avoids him, separates herself from him, refuses to communicate with him, etc.
Nor
can any foundation be construed to the contrary by saying that Christ our Lord
(who gave, without any restriction, supreme and independent power to Peter and
to his See) determined that, in the case of heresy, the Pope’s power would be
dependent upon, and inferior to, the power of the Church formally as such, so
that his power would be subordinated to that of the Church, and not superior as
before [this is the heresy of Conciliarism].
As
to Cajetan’s second proposition, namely, that the Church does not have any power
superior to the Pope; if it be taken without qualification, it has already been
proved at length; for the Church ought to be subject to the Pope; nor is the
Pope’s power derived from the Church, as political power [is derived from the
people]; but it comes immediately from Christ, whom the Pope represents. But it is also evident that, even in the case
of heresy, the power of the Church is not superior to the Pope, inasmuch as we
are concerned with the papal power; firstly, because the power of the Pope is
in no case derived from and originating from the Church, but from Christ;
therefore in no case is the power of the Church superior; also, because the
power of the Pope, inasmuch as it is derived from Christ, was instituted as
being supreme over all the power of the Church that is on earth (as was proven
above from many authorities); but Christ our Lord did not make any exception,
as if there were a case in which that power would be limited and subjected to
another; but always and in respect to all He speaks of it as supreme and
monarchical. But when He mentions the
case of heresy He does not attribute to the Church any superiority over the
Pope, but only commands her to avoid, separate herself from, and not communicate
with one who is a heretic; but none of these indicate any superiority, and they
can be observed without claiming anything of the sort. The power of the Church, therefore, is not
superior to the power of the Pope, even in the case of heresy. Even
the canons confirm this: for they say that the first See is judged by no one;
and this holds true even in the case of infidelity, since the Fathers who were
gathered in the case of Pope Marcellinus said to him: “You must judge yourself.”
The
third proposition follows from the two preceding. For the Church can declare the crime of the
Pope and propose him to the faithful as one who is to be avoided, according to
Divine Law, which commands that heretics be avoided. And the Pope who is to be avoided, as a consequence
of this disposition, is necessarily rendered incapable of being the head of the
Church, since he is a member to be avoided by her, and consequently unable to
exercise an influx on her; therefore, by reason of this power [of declaring the
Pope to be a heretic whom the Church must avoid], the Church dissolves, in a
ministerial and dispositive way, the bond between the papacy and that
person. The consequence is clear: for
when an agent has the power to induce a disposition in a subject, and the disposition
is such that the separation of the form necessarily follows from it (since the
form cannot remain with this disposition in the subject), the agent has power
over the dissolution of the form, and mediately touches the form itself as
having to be separated from the subject—not as having to be destroyed in
itself, as is evident in the agent that corrupts a man; for the agent does not
destroy the form of the man, but induces the dissolution of the form by placing
in the matter a disposition that is incompatible with the form. Therefore, because the Church has the power
to declare that the Pope is to be avoided, she is able to introduce into his
person a disposition that is incompatible with the papacy; and thus the papacy
is dissolved ministerially and dispositively by the Church, but authoritatively
by Christ; even as, in designating him through his election, she gives him the
last disposition needed for him to receive the papacy that Christ our Lord
bestows upon him, and thus she creates a Pope in a ministerial way.
And
if Cajetan sometimes says that the Church has power authoritatively over the
conjunction of the papacy with the person, and its separation from him, but
that she has power ministerially over the papacy itself, he is to be understood
in this way: he means that the Church has the authority to declare the crime of
the Pope, even as she has the authority to designate him as Pope [by papal
election]; and what is authoritative in respect to the declaration is
dispositive and ministerial in relation to the form as having to be joined to
him or separated from him; for, absolutely and of herself, the Church has no
power over the form itself [of the papacy], since the power [of the papacy] is
not subordinated to her.
By
understanding things in this way, we can reconcile the different canons, which
sometimes say that the deposition of the Pope pertains to God alone, and
sometimes that he can be judged by his inferiors in the case of heresy; for it
is true both that the ejection or deposition of the Pope is reserved to God
alone, as the authoritative and principal agent, as is said expressly in the
chapter Ejectionem, distinction 79, and in many other canons cited
above, which say that God has reserved the judgment of the Apostolic See to
himself alone; and also that the Church judges the Pope ministerially and
dispositively by declaring the crime and proposing the Pope as someone who is
to be avoided, as we read in the chapter Si papa, distinction 40, and
the chapter Oves, 2 question 7.
The
arguments of Bellarmine and Suarez against the foregoing opinion [of Cajetan]
are easily refuted. For Bellarmine
objects that the Apostle says that a heretic is to be avoided after two
corrections, that is, after he
manifestly appears to be pertinacious; and that happens before any
excommunication or judicial sentence, as Jerome comments, for heretics depart
from the body of Christ of their own accord [per se]. And his reasoning is this: a non-Christian
cannot be Pope (for he cannot be the head who is not a member); but the heretic
is not a Christian, as the Fathers commonly teach; therefore, the manifest
heretic cannot be Pope. Nor can one
respond that he still has the [baptismal] character; for, if he remained Pope
because of this character, it will never be possible to depose him, as this
character is indelible. Wherefore, the
Fathers—such as Cyprian, Jerome, and Ambrose—teach with one accord that
heretics lack all jurisdiction and power by reason of their heresy, and that
this is so independently of any excommunication.
I
respond that the heretic is to be avoided after two admonitions; that is, after
two admonitions made juridically and by the authority of the Church, and not
according to private judgment; for, if it sufficed for this admonition to be
made by a private individual—and if, when the heresy had been made manifest [by
such private admonitions], but had not [yet] been declared by the Church and
proposed to all so that all might avoid the Pope, the faithful would
nevertheless be obliged to avoid him, great confusion would follow in the
Church; for the heresy of the Pope cannot be public in respect to all the
faithful, unless others relate it to them; but such [private] reports, since
they are not juridical, cannot claim everyone’s belief or oblige them to avoid
the Pope: hence, just as the Church, by designating the man, proposed him
juridically to all as the elected Pope, so too, it is necessary that she
depose him by declaring him a heretic and proposing him as one to be
avoided. Hence, we see from the practice
of the Church that this is how it has been done; for, in the case of the
deposition of a Pope, his cause was handled in a general Council before he was
considered not to be Pope, as we have related above. It is not true, then, that the Pope ceases to
be Pope by the very fact [ipso facto] that he is a heretic, even a
public one, before any sentence of the Church and before she proposes him to the faithful as one who is to be
avoided. Nor does Jerome exclude the
judgment of the Church (especially in so grave a matter as the deposition of a
Pope) when he says that a heretic departs from the body of Christ of his own
accord [per se]; rather, he is judging the quality of the crime, which
of its very nature [per se] excludes one from the Church—provided that
the crime is declared by the Church—without the need for any superadded
censure; for, although heresy separates one from the Church by its very nature
[per se], nevertheless, this separation is not thought to have been
made, as far as we are concerned [quoad nos], without that
declaration. Likewise, we respond to his
reasoning in this way: one who is not a Christian, both in himself and in
relation to us [quoad se et quoad nos], cannot be Pope; however, if in
himself he is not a Christian (because he has lost the faith) but in relation
to us has not yet been juridically declared as an infidel or heretic (no matter
how manifestly he be such according to private judgment), he is still a member
of the Church as far as we are concerned; and consequently he is its head. It is necessary, therefore, to have the
judgment of the Church, by which he is proposed to us as someone who is not a
Christian, and who is to be avoided; and at that point he ceases to be Pope in
relation to us [quoad nos]; and we further conclude that he had not
ceased to be Pope before [the declaration], even in himself, since all of his
acts were valid in themselves.
The
second objection is this: the Church cannot have power
over the bond between the papacy and the person without having power over the
papacy itself; for neither does the Pope, when he deposes a bishop, do anything
more than destroy the bond between him and his episcopacy—for he does not
destroy the episcopacy itself; therefore, if the Church has power over the bond
that exists between the papacy and the person, consequently she has power over
both the papacy and the person of the Pope.
And this reasoning is confirmed by the fact that the Pope is deposed
against his will, and therefore is penalized in such a deposition; but to
inflict a penalty is proper to a superior and a judge; therefore the Church,
when she deposes a Pope—that is, inflicts on him the penalty of deposition—has
superiority over the person of the Pope [which is impossible; therefore (Suarez
concludes) the Church cannot depose a heretical Pope; but Jesus Christ does it
immediately, as soon as the declaration of heresy is made by the Church].
Finally, he who has power over both the parts—that is, over their conjunction—has power in an unqualified sense over the whole, even as one who generates a man has power in an unqualified sense over the whole man; therefore, if the Church has power over the conjunction of the papacy with the person, she has power over the Pope in an unqualified sense, contrary to Cajetan’s assertion.
Finally, he who has power over both the parts—that is, over their conjunction—has power in an unqualified sense over the whole, even as one who generates a man has power in an unqualified sense over the whole man; therefore, if the Church has power over the conjunction of the papacy with the person, she has power over the Pope in an unqualified sense, contrary to Cajetan’s assertion.
I
respond that the Church, when she deposes a Pope, does not have power over him
in the same way as the Pope has power over a bishop when he deposes him; for
the Pope, in depriving a bishop of his episcopacy, acts on him as one who is
subject to him, and whose power is subordinated to him and dependent on him,
and which he can limit and constrain; hence, although he removes the episcopacy
from the person without destroying the episcopacy, nevertheless, he takes it
away by reason of his superiority over the person (even in respect to the power
that the person has, since the same is subordinate to him); and because of this
he moves the power away from the person, and not just the person away from the
power. The Church, however, takes away
the papacy, not because she has any superiority over that power, but rather
through the ministerial and dispositive power by which she is able to induce a
disposition [in the person of the Pope] that is incompatible with the papacy,
in the way explained above.
As
to the supporting argument, I respond that the Pope is deposed against his will
ministerially and dispositively by the Church, but authoritatively by Christ
our Lord; hence it is by Christ, and not by the Church, that he is punished in
the proper sense.
To
the last argument, I say that he who has power over the conjunction of the
parts has power over the whole in an unqualified sense; but this is not the
case if he has a merely ministerial and dispositive power over such a
conjunction—unless we are discussing natural bodies, in which the physical
dispositions have a natural connection with the very being of the whole; for,
when an agent communicates being to a natural body by producing dispositions
that unite its parts, it produces the whole natural body in an unqualified
sense; but because in moral beings the disposition has only a moral connection
with the form, and this connection is because of a voluntary institution, he
who disposes the moral being is not considered to produce the whole being in an
unqualified sense and authoritatively, but as it were ministerially. This is comparable to how, if the Pope were
to grant someone the power to determine which places have privileges of gaining
indulgences and which do not, the desigation that this person makes would not take
away or grant the indulgences principally and authoritatively, but only
ministerially.
_____________________
[1] Cursus
Theologicus
of John of St. Thomas, Tome 6. Questions
1-7 on Faith. Disputation 8. Article 2 ~