Several months ago the website Non Veni Pacem posted an article
titled, “A Friendly Challenge to Robert Siscoe,” by "Smith" a regular commenter on the site. The
Challenge was in response to an article I wrote on the Peaceful and Universal Acceptance’
(here), which was intended to demonstrate that the legitimacy of Francis' pontificate is an
infallible dogmatic fact.
Smith offered a number of objections to the
article, but the main one – the one he himself referred to
as his Major
Point – is that “the designation of dogmatic fact as to the validity of a papal
election can only apply to past popes,” not present Popes.”
Smith defended his position by stating that
dogmatic facts require the assent of divine faith, and then argued that this level of assent is
only given to the legitimacy of Pope due to his connection with a “primary dogma” (by which he
means a revealed truth). If there is no connection between the Pope
and a primary dogma, he contends, his legitimacy does not require the assent of divine faith, and therefore it cannot be an infallible dogmatic
fact.
He then provided several
arguments to justify his contention that only past Popes can be
connected with a "primary dogma" and attempted to show why several of my arguments were erroneous. He further argued that two of the five
quotations I included in my article referred to past Pope, not current
Popes, and claimed that these quotations further confirm his position.
That seems to be the main thrust of his
argument. I will also take the opportunity to respond to an objection that was raised by Bishop Garcia, and another by Fred Martinez of the Catholic Monitor, in response to a
two-part article I wrote for One Peter Five that defended the same doctrine. (Part I, Part II).
Smith: I have the book True or False Pope, and
have read it a couple of times. I think it is literally monumental; an
extremely scholarly work, upon which extraordinary diligence has been
exercised. In spite of the huge respect I have for it I must admit that
there were a very few assertions made therein that seemed to me to be lacking
the necessary support of fact and/or logic. One of these was the claim
that, once a pope is accepted with moral unanimity of the Church, that very
fact guarantees the validity of his election.
Siscoe: Thank you for
the compliment about True or False Pope?. Wait until you see the
expanded second edition (with an additional 300 pages) that will be coming out
soon. It contains some real surprises
for the Sedevacantists.
Regarding your statement
about PUA seeming to be deficient in logic, it may seem that way at first, but
if you delve into it and think about it, not only will you come to see the
logic in it, but you will realize how important and even necessary it is – especially in the present papal crisis.
I can also assured you that this
doctrine is one that gives the Sedevacantists (at least the
few who have studied it and understand it) the most difficulties. Listen to what the Sedevacantist
apologist, John Lane, admitted when he was asked why he accepts the Pontificate
of John XXIII (whom he could not deny had been universally accepted as Pope):
“Because the theologians say that the adherence
of the whole Church to any given claimant is in itself a proof that all of the
necessary requisites [i.e., conditions] for validity are present. The reason
for this is the indefectibility of the Church, which cannot adhere to a false
visible head. It would in some ways be more convenient if this doctrine did
not exist, but it does. J By the way, I think that this doctrine is
chiefly what Archbishop Lefebvre had in view when he commented in the late '70s
that the See of Rome could not be vacant because of the necessary visibility of
the Church. In any case, it is certainly
a powerful argument for sedeplenism [i.e. against Sedevcantism], which is perhaps why most sedevacantists
never mention it.J”[1]
That’s quite an
admission, but in his unguarded moment, Mr. Lane admitted what anyone who
understands the doctrine will already know, namely, that Sedevacantism cannot hold up in the face of this doctrine.
I should also clarify
that the reason he only concedes that it proves the legitimacy of John XXIII’s
papacy, is not because he believes the doctrine only applies to past popes, but because he has not been able to come up with any excuse, however
weak, to justify the assertion that John XXIII's election was not peacefully and universally
accepted by the Church.
Lane’s fellow
Sedevacantist apologist, John Daly, likewise readily admits that doctrine is
true, and that it applies to the current Pope.
In a public exchange from 2006, Mr. Daly’s interlocutor wrote: “Cardinal Billot
and other theologians speak about the fact that universal adherence to a
certain man as pope results in an infallible fact that the man is indeed,
pope.” To which Daly replied: “Yes, if the universal Church with moral
unanimity peacefully accept a man as legitimate pope, he must indeed
be a legitimate pope.”
None of the informed
Sedevacantists deny the doctrine itself. What they do instead is try to
find ways of explaining why the recent Popes have not been peacefully accepted by the entire Church. But all such arguments are easily refuted and
I suspect they realize it. That explains
why, as Lane admitted, rather than presenting unconvincing arguments in an
attempt to show why PUA does not prove the legitimacy of all the recent Popes,
most Sedevacansits simply avoid the doctrine and “never mention it.”
I recently happened
across a public exchange from 2006, in which Lane was attempting to explain PUA
to his fellow Sedevacantists, some of whom were unable to grasp it. What
I found nteresting is that he was being presented with
the identical objections that I’ve received in the past few months, and almost all of his answers were identical to my
own. The only difference is that Lane lacked clarity on a few points – such
as the meaning of “peaceful” (which John of St. Thomas explains) - the knowledge
of which would have removed any reasonable doubt in his mind that the election
of all the recent Popes have indeed been peacefully and universally accepted.
Here is one exchange
between Lane and one of his fellow Sedes that I found interesting:
Ken: “I, too,
find this [doctrine] nearly inexplicable. In God's eyes, a man is
either the Pope or he isn't, and whether or not we believe him to be or not to
be (Hamlet) does not determine the facts.”
Lane: “The opinion of men doesn't determine
anything. The Church is a visible institution and therefore visible facts are
determinate, not secret ones. The fact that men may or may not notice them is
secondary and dependent upon those objective realities. Distinct from this is
the adherence of the whole Church to a given claimant. It is not a question of
‘opinion’ but rather of ecclesiastical unity, precisely because it involves the
whole Church. (…)
“I understand that these things are somewhat
difficult but you'll have to trust the canonists and theologians who explain
them. I can tell you, for what it's worth, that once you have spent
time pondering these things they become clear. You can ‘see’ the realities and
the various distinctions. They take on a clarity which makes the explanations
of the authorities actually ‘explain’ them for you. But I am not sure
that everybody has the kind of mind which can grapple successfully with these
kinds of abstractions.”[2]
I don’t know if he is
correct about some people lacking the ability to grasp the doctrine, but I do
know that those who are able to grasp the principles (provided they are not simply out to prove, at all costs, that the recent Popes were not true Pope), will no longer doubt the validity of Benedict’s resignation or that of Francis’ election.
Now to Smith's objections…
The Legitimacy of a Pope
is a Dogmatic Fact, not a Dogma
Smith: “If I have your
position correct, the guts of it all is this: Assertion: It is a dogma
that once a pope is accepted with moral unanimity by the Church, he is a valid
pope, regardless of any antecedent irregularities.”
Siscoe: No, the legitimacy of a Pope is not a dogma (primary
object of infallibility), but rather a dogmatic fact (secondary object of
infallibility). A dogma is a formally revealed truth (contained
in Scripture or Tradition); a dogmatic fact is a truth that is related to
the revealed deposit and necessary for its preservation. The identity of
a Pope is not a truth contained in Scripture or Tradition, but it is something
that must be known with infallible certitude, not only because the Pope is the
rule of faith (in the doctrines he defines), but also because he is the head of
the universal Church and principle of unity.
Smith: “It was most certainly not defined as a dogma by Martin V
that a pope accepted with moral unanimity by the Church is definitely a valid
pope …
Siscoe: Correct. The teaching of Martin V
is not a dogmatic definition. It is one of 39 questions defined by the
Council of Constance to be proposed to those who were suspected of heresy, or
to those returning from heresy, in order to determine if they believe and profess
the faith of the Church. The question that was defined is whether they believe that the currently
reigning Pope is the successor of St. Peter and possesses supreme authority in
the Church. Now, since those suspected
of heresy are only interrogated concerning matters of faith, the theologians explain that this definition of Pope
Martin shows the legitimacy of a Pope – the one recognized as such by the
hierarchy at the time - is de fide. This point will be discussed later.
Smith: But your contention is not this [i.e., that it is a
dogma], but that it is a matter of the *secondary* object of Faith; that is,
you say it is a dogmatic fact. But this does not work for present popes, only
past ones. Why? A dogmatic fact is one that is so connected to a
*primary* fact of faith that, without it, that primary fact becomes impossible.
In the present question, we can take as an example the dogmatic fact that Pius
IX was a real pope. Why is this a matter of divine Faith? There are
two reasons: First and most important is that he himself defined the
dogma of the Immaculate Conception. If he wasn’t a real pope, that is no
longer, and never was, a dogma. If the Church were to come to believe
a “dogma” through a supposed solemn papal declaration that never occurred
because the supposed pope was not a pope at all, it wouldn’t be a dogma, so the
Church would be in error on a matter supposed to be infallible, thus the Church
would be fallible, which would mean the Church had defected.
Siscoe: But if there’s no certainty that the man the Church
recognizes as Pope is the true Pope before he defines a dogma,
why would it become certain that he was Pope after he did so? It
wouldn’t. Does anyone believe those who reject
the validity of Francis’ election would accept him as Pope if he defined a
dogma? Highly unlikely. If they personally disagreed with the dogma he
defined, they would simply reject it on the basis that it wasn’t defined by a
true Pope.
Nor would defining a dogma resolve the doubts of
Catholics who are unsure if Francis
is the Pope. On the contrary, they would
doubt the dogmatic definition precisely because they doubted his Papacy. Any antecedent doubt concerning
the legitimacy of a Pope will necessarily result in consequent doubt
about any doctrines he defined.
This shows why it must be infallibly certain that the man the
Church recognized as Pope is, in fact, the true Pope even before he defines a doctrine.
Smith: “Secondly, the indefectibility of the Church is a primary
dogma, but that requires an unbroken line of popes, because a
pope is an essential requirement in the constitution of the Church as such, as
decreed by Divine Law. If Pius IX were not a true pope, the line of succession
would have been broken (especially considering his long reign).
Siscoe: The Divine constitution of the Church not only
requires an unbroken line of past Popes. It also requires that
the man who is currently recognized as Pope is, in fact, the legitimate Pope. As
Fr. Hunter, S.J., explains in Outlines of Dogmatic Theology (1894),
if the entire body of bishops were to recognize (present tense) a false Pope as their
head, the Divine constitution of the Church would be ruined:
Fr. Hunter: “Dogmatic Facts: - But besides these speculative
truths, there are certain matters of fact concerning which the Church can judge
with infallibly certainty. These are called by many writers dogmatic facts
[.]
“First, then, the Church is infallible when she
declares what person holds the office of Pope; for if the person of the Pope
were uncertain, it would be uncertain what Bishops were in communion with the
Pope; but according to the Catholic faith, as will be proved hereafter,
communion with the Pope is a condition for the exercise of the function of
teaching by the body of Bishops (n. 208); if then the uncertainty could not be
cleared up, the power of teaching could not be exercised, and Christ's promise
(St. Matt, xxviii. 20; and n. 199, II.) would be falsified, which is
impossible.
“This argument is in substance the same as
applies to other cases of dogmatic facts. Also, it affords an answer to a
much vaunted objection to the claims
of the Catholic Church, put forward by writers who think that they find proof in history that the election of a
certain Pope was simoniacal and invalid, and that the successor
was elected by Cardinals who owed their appointment to the simoniacal intruder;
from which it is gathered that the Papacy has been vacant since that time.
A volume might be occupied if we attempt to expose all the frailness of the
argument which is supposed to lead to this startling conclusion; but it
is enough to say that if the Bishops agree in recognizing a certain man as
Pope, they are certainly right, for otherwise the body of the Bishops would
be separated from their head, and the Divine constitution
of the Church would be ruined.” (Hunter, Outlines of Dogmatic
Theology, Volume I (New York, Cincinnati, Chicago, Benzinger Brothers, 1894)
ch. VI, N. 211.
You see, the Divine constitution of the Church doesn’t merely
require that all previous popes were legitimate.
It requires that the man who the entire Church presently recognizes as Pope, is the legitimate Pope. No one publicly questioned Francis' Pontificate during the first year, and the entire episcopate has always recognized him as Pope. This not only proves that Francis is the Pope, it also proves that Benedict’s resignation was valid.
And notice what Hunter said above about the “much vaunted
objection” of allegedly invalid papal elections, resulting in invalid
cardinal electors being appointed, eventually resulting in an end of the line of true
Popes. This was a popular argument used by Protestant scholars in the 19th
century. They dug up numerous historical examples of illegal papal elections, in an effort to prove that the line of Popes had come to an end.
How did the Catholic apologists reply? What the Catholic apologists did not do is attempt to refute each
allegation of an illegal election. Not
only would such an endeavor have taken years, it would have never resolved
the controversy with any degree of certitude.
The way the Catholic canonists and theologians refuted these Protestants, was by appealing to the doctrine of the peaceful and universal
acceptance, which is all that is required to prove the validity of the problematic or controversial papal election. The following is just one example of a 19th century Catholic canonist appealing to the doctrine to refute this Protestant objection:
“Mr. Gladstone need not
be alarmed about the papal succession.
Independently of all previous proceedings, the acceptance of Martin V by
the Universal Church as lawful Pope proves
that his election was canonical and legitimate; for the recognition of the true
Pope is a dogmatic fact in which the Universal Church cannot err.” (Rev. James
Kavanagh, D.D., A Reply to Mr. Gladstone’s Vaticanism, Dublin, James Guffy,
1895, p. 54)
The universal acceptance was the primary argument used by the Catholics
scholars to refute the Protestant claims of invalidly elected Popes – and they
used the same argument to prove the legitimacy of the currently reigning Pope’s
election. It should also be noted that
most of the objections raised by the Protestants at the time were far more persuasive
than those being used to deny the validity of Francis’ election today.
Interregnums/Interregna
Smith: But there HAVE been interregnums, and no
one knows exactly how long one could last before it constitutes a break in the
line. It could be as long as a generation, and probably not longer. But therefore, as
long as a *current* putatative pope reigns, there is the possibility that his
election was invalid, regardless of universal acceptance.
Siscoe: The Divine Constitution of the Church does not
require that there always be a reigning Pope, but it does require that a man presently recognized
by the entire Church as Pope, is the legitimate Pope, for the reason Fr.
Hunter mentioned above. Cardinal Billot teaches the same:
Cardinal Billot: “God
can permit that at times a vacancy in the Apostolic See be prolonged for a long
time. He can also permit that doubt arise about the legitimacy of this or that
election. He cannot however permit that the whole Church accept as
Pontiff him who is not so truly and legitimately.”
Regarding how long an interregnum could last, the
best answer is given by Salaverri. Certain men are appointed by the Pope to carry on the government of the Church during the time of the
vacancy (e.g., the Major Penitentiary Cardinal, the Camerlengo, etc.).
Salverri teaches that the Church can continue to function as long as these men live, but no longer. (Sacrae Theologiae Summa 1B, I.3.3. Scholium 5).
Smith: MAJOR POINT: The designation of dogmatic fact as to the validity of a
papal election can only apply to *past* popes.
Siscoe: Your Major Point is also your Major Error, and the cause
is a failure to realize that the legitimacy of the presently reigning
Pope has a connection to multiple “primary dogmas.” One example is found in the
article on dogmatic facts in the Catholic Encyclopedia (1909), which uses the
dogma that the Pope is the successor of St. Peter to prove why the validity of
the election of the presently reigning Pope (Pius X) was a dogmatic fact:
“The following questions
involve dogmatic facts in the wider sense: Is Pius X, for instance, really and
truly Roman Pontiff [1909], duly elected and recognized by the Universal
Church? This is connected with dogma,
for it is a dogma of faith that every pontiff duly elected and recognized by
the universal Church is a successor of Peter.” (Catholic Encyclopedia)[3]
Smith: Firstly, and by far most importantly, it is utterly
impossible that a determination of the *present* juridical status of anyone can
be a matter of divine Faith.
Siscoe: Incorrect again, but this error does flow logically
from your “Major Error”. The same Catholic encyclopedia article goes on to
explain that the validity of Pius X’s election must be accepted with “divine
faith” because of the connection between
a validly elected Pope and the dogma that the Pope is the successor of St.
Peter.
“Some theologians hold
that definitions of dogmatic facts, and especially of dogmatic facts in the
wider acceptation of the term, are believed by Divine faith. For
instance, the proposition, ‘every pope duly elected is the successor of Peter’,
is formally revealed. Then, say these theologians, the proposition, ‘Pius X has
been duly elected pope’, only shows that Pius X is included in the general
revealed proposition that ‘every pope duly elected is the successor of
Peter’. And they conclude that the proposition, ‘Pius X is [present tense] successor to
Peter", is a formally revealed proposition; that it is believed by Divine
faith;”
Cardinal
Journet provides an identical explanation in The Church of the Word Incarnate.
(see comment about ecclesiastical faith) [1]
Do Fr. Berry and Van Noort refer to Past Popes?
Smith: “Firstly, your citation of Berry is not to the point,
because the context of his discussion concerns PAST popes, not present ones.
Scratch Berry. He seems to support my position, not yours.”
Siscoe: No, Fr. Berry refers to the currently reigning
Pope. You may have been confused because the publication date of the book
I referenced was 1955 (when Pius XII was Pope), but the book was originally
published in 1927, during the reign of Pius XI. Here is the same quotation as
found on page 507 of the book published in 1927:
"DOGMATIC FACTS. A dogmatic fact is one
that has not been revealed, yet is so intimately connected with a doctrine of
faith that without certain knowledge of the fact there can be no certain
knowledge of the doctrine. For example, was the [First] Vatican Council truly
ecumenical? Was Pius IX a legitimate pope? Was the election of Pius XI
valid? Such questions must be decided with certainty before
decrees issued by any council or pope can be accepted as infallibly true or
binding on the Church. It is evident, then, that the Church must be infallible
in judging of such facts, and since the Church is infallible in believing as
well as in teaching, it follows that the practically unanimous consent
of the bishops and faithful in accepting a council as ecumenical, or a Roman
Pontiff as legitimately elected, gives absolute and infallible certainty of the
fact." (Berry, The Church of Christ, London: Herder Book Co. 1927, p.
507).
Notice, he says the legitimacy of the currently reigning Pope must
be known with certainty before he issues any decrees (if not, they would
be in doubt), and says the way it is known with certainty is by the “the
practically unanimous consent of the bishops and faithful” recognizing him as
Pope.
Smith: Secondly, your citations of Van Noort: The first citation
clearly also addresses past popes, not present ones.
Siscoe: Nope, Van Noort refers to the presently reigning Pope
as well. His book was published in 1957,
during the reign of Pius XII. Here’s the quote:
"Assertion 2: The Church’s infallibility
extends to dogmatic facts. This proposition is theologically certain. A
dogmatic fact is a fact not contained in the sources of revelation, [but] on
the admission of which depends the knowledge or certainty of a dogma or of a
revealed truth. The following questions are concerned with dogmatic facts: ‘Was
the [First] Vatican Council a legitimate ecumenical council? Is the Latin
Vulgate a substantially faithful translation of the original books of the
Bible? Was Pius XII legitimately elected Bishop of
Rome? One can readily see that on these facts hang the questions of
whether the decrees of the Vatican Council are infallible, whether the Vulgate
is truly Sacred Scripture, whether Pius XII is to be [present
tense] recognized as supreme ruler of the universal Church." (Van
Noort, Christ’s Church, (Westminster, Maryland: Newman Press, originally
published in 1957, p.112).
Notice the reason he said the legitimacy of Pius
XII’s election is a dogmatic fact. It’s not because of the connection
between Pius XII and the dogma of the Assumption that he defined, but because
of his connection to the dogma that the Pope is the supreme ruler of the
universal Church.
Allow me to provide one additional quote that confirms the
same.
In the following quote, Fr. Hurter says the legitimacy of the present Pope is a dogmatic fact based on
the connection between the Pope and the dogma that the Roman Pontiff is the
center of Catholic unity. The following is taken from his book, Theologiae
Dogmaticae Compendium, which was published in 1885, during the pontificate
of Leo XII:
[Dogmatic facts] include
things of this sort: that the Sacred Scriptures
we use are genuine; that the Councils of Nicaea, Ephesus,
Trent, etc. were legitimate; that Pius IX, Leo
XIII, etc. were elected legitimately and
consequently were legitimate successors to Peter as Bishops of Rome.
Just see what would result if you would let any of these things be called into
doubt. Definitions issued during Councils would not have certainty. There would
be no sure way of determining the center of Catholic
unity. In short, what would result is the uprooting of faith
itself and the destruction of Revelation. (Hurter, S.J. Theologiae Dogmaticae
Compendium (1885) I.338, Thesis LV).
So, we’ve seen that the presently reigning Pope
is connected to the dogma that 1) the Pope is the successor of St. Peter, 2)
the he is the head of the universal Church (with supreme jurisdiction), and 3)
the principle of unity. Not just the
dogma that the Pope is the rule of faith (i.e. possesses the authority to
defined doctrines that must be held de
fide).
In the next objection, you quote John of St.
Thomas and then comment on what he wrote:
Smith: “…we discuss whether or not it is de fide that
this specific person, who *has been* legitimately elected…” (John of St.
Thomas). Note the past tense. And please don’t suggest that
it is past *progressive*, thus implying something that has occurred and is
continuing up to the present.
Siscoe: The event that happened in the past is the election.
If the current Pope was legitimately elected (past tense), it means he became,
and therefore is, the legitimate Pope
(present tense). The entire sentence shows that this is what John of St.
Thomas meant:
John of St. Thomas:
"In the present controversy we discuss whether or not it is de
fide that this specific person, who has been legitimately elected
[past tense], is the Pope and the head of the Church [present tense], as well
as the degree of certitude with which this proposition is to be
held."
You’re objection
actually raises an important point that needs to be clarified. When the
theologians refer to the legitimacy of a Pope being a dogmatic fact, what they
are referring to is the legitimacy of the election. The
dogmatic fact is that the election (past tense) was valid,
since this is what determines if the man is (present tense)
the head of the universal Church. Dogmatic facts are historical facts that are related to the revealed deposit; and the
historical fact that determines the legitimacy of a Pope is the validity of his
election.
You can see this in the
quotation from Van Noort that was quoted above. Here it is again:
‘Was the Vatican Council a legitimate ecumenical
council? (…) Was Pius XII legitimately elected [past tense] Bishop of Rome? One can readily see that on
these facts hang the questions of whether the decrees of the Vatican Council
are infallible (…) whether Pius XII is to be [present tense]
recognized as supreme ruler of the universal Church."
Also notice what Fr.
Berry wrote in the quotation cited above. He didn’t ask if Pius XI (the
present Pope) was the legitimate Pope. What he asked is whether
“the election of Pius XI was valid?” Sometimes the legitimacy of the Pope himself
is referred to as a dogmatic fact, but strictly speaking the dogmatic fact
concerns the validity of his election.
This is an important point to keep in mind.
Quotation from Van Noort on the Ordinary and
Universal Magisterium
Smith: “Your citations of Van
Noort … The second one does indeed concern present popes. His
book was published in 1957, and therefore written before that, and Pius XII
died in October of 1958. Here, Van Noort claims that Pius XII is guaranteed to
be a valid pope by the infallible Ordinary Magisterium, as follows:
“The Church possesses infallibility not only when she is
defining some matters in solemn fashion, but also when she is exercising the
full weight of her authority through her ordinary and universal teaching.
Consequently, we must hold with an absolute assent, which we call
‘ecclesiastical faith,’ the following theological truths:..Pius XII is the
legitimate successor of St. Peter.”
Most unfortunately, there is a completely irredeemable and fatal
flaw of fact in this reasoning. What Van Noort seems to forget here is that the
Universal Ordinary Infallible Magisterium requires universality not only in
space, but in time. In other words, the bishops’ unanimous teaching of a
particular truth must be not only something they, worldwide, are agreed on NOW,
but also something which they have Traditionally always agreed upon. In support
of this I have to adduce your OWN exposition of this fact, given in True or
False Pope, pp. 439ff, in particular p. 440: “Ordinary acts of the
magisterium…to be considered as belonging to the Church’s [infallible]
teaching…are infallible only insofar as they fit into the constant
teaching…reflect or echo the permanent teaching and unchanging Faith of the
Church.” (Canon Berthod)
Siscoe: There’s an important distinction that you’ve missed. Universality in time is
necessary for a revealed truth (which has not been solemnly
defined), to be infallibly proposed as an object of divine and catholic
Faith by the ordinary and universal Magisterium (OUM), but it is not
required for dogmatic facts to be infallibly known and taught by
the OUM.
Context: In the pages of
True or False Pope that you referred to, what is being discussed is the infallibility
of the ordinary and universal Magisterium according to the teaching of Dei
Filius (from Vatican I), which is strictly limited to revealed
truths.
If you look at the top of page 438, you will see that we included
the phrase “according to Dei Filius” (in
parenthesis) just before explaining the conditions for infallibility of the
OUM. This was done intentionally, since the conditions for a doctrine to be
proposed as an object of divine and Catholic faith by the OUM (which is what De
Filius is referring to) are not the same as the conditions for a dogmatic fact
to be proposed infallibly, as an object of faith.
Regarding the quotation from Canon Berthod, he too is commenting
on De Filius, and therefore is referring exclusively to revealed
truths. If you have the book, “Pope or Church?”, flip to page 57 and you will
see that Canon Berthod quotes De Filius directly before commenting on it. The
quotation we included at the top of page 440 of True or False Pope? is from
the very next page 58, where he addresses the conditions.
But the question that remains is why an undefined doctrine (a revealed truth) requires ‘universality in time’ to be infallibly proposed by the OUM, when the
legitimacy of a Pope does not. For the answer, flip to page 439, below
the heading “Definitively Proposed.” There we explain that only doctrines
that have been definitively proposed are an object of
faith. The difference between a revealed truth that has been proposed
definitively by a solemn definition, and one that has been proposed definitively
by the OUM, is that the former occurs by a single definitive act of
a pope or a council, while the latter acquires a definitive character, not
by a single act, but by a multitude of non-definitive acts occurring over
the course of the centuries, which coalesce in such a way that the entire
Catholic world knows (or should know) the teaching is de fide, even
without it having to be defined.
And therein lies the difference between how an undefined ‘revealed
truth’ is known to belong to the faith, and how a Pope
is known to be Pope. To know if an individual is the
Pope, we don’t look back over the course of the centuries in an attempt to
discern the fact. We look to the election.
When the cardinals present the newly elected Pope to the Catholic
world ("Habemus Papam"), it is analogous to the single definitive act that takes
place with a solemn definition, which removes all ambiguity about what is
proposed for belief. If the man presented by the cardinals as having been
elected is accepted by the entire ecclesia docens (teaching
Church), the legitimacy of the Pope is guaranteed by the infallibility of the
ordinary and universal Magisterium.
The Election of a Pope vis-à-vis a Doctrinal
Definition
John of St. Thomas compares the election of a Pope by a conclave
to the definition of a doctrine by a council. The difference, he
says, is that when a council defines a doctrine it becomes de fide when it is
accepted by the Pope, whereas when a conclave elects a Pope, his legitimacy
becomes de fide when it is accepted by the Church. He writes:
“The Church accepts the
election and the elect as a matter of faith, because as she receives him as the
infallible rule of faith, and as the supreme head to whom
she is united—for the unity of the Church depends upon her union with
him.
"TO THE OBJECTION
that there must be someone to propose this truth to the Church as de fide, I
respond that the election and the one elected are proposed by the cardinals,
not in their own person, but in the person of the Church and by her power—for
she it is who committed to them the power of electing the pope and of declaring
him to have been elected. Wherefore they, in this respect and for this
task, are the Church herself representatively. Thus the cardinals, or whoever else
the Church (that is, the Pope) has legitimately designated to do the electing,
represent the Church in all that concerns the election of her head, the
successor of Peter.
“Just as the pope
gathers the bishops together in a Council, and yet its confirmation and the
ultimate sentence in matters of faith depend upon him, so the congregation of
cardinals elects the pope, and declares that he has been elected, and yet it is
the Church, whose ministers they are, that by its acceptance ultimately
confirms as a truth of faith the fact that this man is truly the highest rule
of faith and the supreme pontiff. Wherefore, if the
cardinals elect him in a questionable manner, the Church can correct their
election, as the Council of Constance determined in its 41st session.
Hence, the proposition [i.e., that he is the legitimate Pope] is rendered de
fide, as already has been explained, by the acceptance of the
Church, and that alone, even before the pope himself defines
anything.”
By the election, the Cardinals propose the man to the Church as
Pope (single act). The acceptance of the Pope by the Church – and
especially by the bishops dispersed throughout the world - is what provides the
infallible certitude that renders the legitimacy of the Pope de fide,
just as the Pope’s acceptance of a doctrine defined by a council is what
renders the doctrine de fide.
Notice that John of St. Thomas’ explanation is identical to that
of Fr. Berry:
Fr. Berry: “Was the
election of Pius XI valid? (…) the practically unanimous consent of the
bishops and faithful in accepting (…) a Roman Pontiff as legitimately elected,
gives absolute and infallible certainty of the fact."
John of St. Thomas goes
on to explain when the legitimacy of a Pope is a matter of
faith (de fide).
"All that remains
to be determined, then, is the exact moment when the
acceptance of the Church becomes sufficient to render the proposition [i.e.,
that this man is Pope] de fide. Is it as soon as the cardinals propose the
elect to the faithful who are in the immediate locality, or only when knowledge
of the election has sufficiently spread through the whole world, wherever the
Church is to be found?
"I REPLY that (as
we have said above) the unanimous election of the cardinals and their
declaration is similar to a definition given by the bishops at a Council
legitimately gathered. Moreover, the acceptance of the Church is, for us, like
a confirmation of this declaration. Now, the acceptance of the Church is
realized both negatively, by the fact that the Church does not contradict the
news of the election wherever it becomes known, and positively, by the gradual
acceptance of the prelates of the Church, beginning with the place of the
election, and spreading throughout the rest of the world. As soon
as men see or hear that a Pope has been elected, and that the election is not
contested, they are obliged to believe that that man is the Pope, and to accept
him."
During the time John of St. Thomas’ was writing it likely took
weeks for news of the election to spread, but it our day it is broadcast
throughout the world in real time. The fact that Francis election was not
immediately contested by members of the Magisterium proves that his election
was valid.
Smith: Secondly, there
is grave question as to whether Francis was “canonically elected”. In fact,
that’s the whole thrust of the Substantial Error argument; that he was NOT
canonically elected.
Siscoe: This objection reveals a lack of understanding of the
doctrine. The universal acceptance of
Francis not only proves that he was
canonically elected. It also proves that Benedict’s abdication was valid.
I should clarify that the phrase used by John of St. Thomas is not
canonically elected but canonically accepted (canonice
acceptatus) – that is, accepted by the Church as having been
canonically elected. Such acceptance doesn’t prove that there were no
shenanigans associated with the election, but it does prove that the election
achieved its desired effect. It also suffices to remedy any technical defect
in the election, as the Council of Constance teaches (per JST).
As John of St. Thomas explains in his treatise, the validity or
lack thereof of an election cannot be determined by the Church based
on knowledge of what transpired behind the closed doors of the conclave, since
the participants are all bound to secrecy under the pain of
excommunication. There must, therefore, be an external sign that provides
the infallible assurance the Church needs; and indeed there is.
The theologians and canonists have consistently taught that the
universal acceptance of the Church is that external sign. As the famous
canonist, Fr. Wernz, explains, the universal acceptance is “the sign and
the infallible effect of a valid election.” (Ius Canonicum II,
Gregorianae, Romae, 1943, 520-521). Arnaldo
de Salveira notes that this is the common teaching:
Silveira: In respect to a doubtful Pope, it is necessary
to make it very clear here that the peaceful acceptance of a Pope by the whole
Church is ‘a sign and an infallible effect of a valid election’. This is the common teaching of the authors.” (L’Ordo Missae de
Paul VI: Qu’en penser?, Paris, 1980, p. 72).
Now, the universal acceptance is not only an infallible effect of
a valid election, but it is also (logically), an infallible sign that all conditions required for validity were
satisfied – such as the condition
that the papal office was vacant at the time of the election. Here is Cardinal Billot’s explanation of this
point:
Cardinal Billot: “one
point must be considered absolutely incontrovertible and placed firmly above
any doubt whatever: the adhesion of the universal Church will be always, in
itself, an infallible sign of the legitimacy of a determined
Pontiff, and therefore also of the existence of all the conditions required
for legitimacy itself. (…) Therefore, from the moment in
which the Pope is accepted by the Church and united to her as the head to the
body, it is no longer permitted to raise doubts about a possible vice
of election or a possible lack of any condition whatsoever necessary for
legitimacy. For the aforementioned adhesion of the Church heals in the root
all fault in the election and proves infallibly the existence of all the
required conditions.”
Notice, from the moment the Pope is accepted by the entire Church,
it is no longer permitted to raise doubts about any defects in the election or
the lack of any conditions required for validity.
The fact that Francis
was accepted as Pope by the entire Church after his election provides
infallible certainty that he became the Pope. And if it is infallibly certain
that Francis became Pope, it is equally certain that Benedict’s resignation was
valid, since a valid resignation is one of the conditions required for Francis to have been validly elected.
This is what some people have a hard time grasping, but it is not
difficult to understand.
If someone turns on a light switch and the room lights up, it
provides infallible certainty that there is a working light bulb in the
socket. But that’s not all it proves. It also logically proves that the
switch works (condition 1); that the wires are connected from the switch to the
light fixture (condition 2); and that the light fixture itself works (condition
3). The fact that the light comes on when you flip the switch, not only
proves there is a working bulb, it also proves that the conditions required for
the bulb to come on were met.
So likewise, if the cardinals elect a Pope (flipping the switch),
and his election is not at once contested by the Church (room lights up), it
not only provides infallible certainty that the man is the legitimate Pope
(working light bulb), but is also proves that the papal office was vacant at
the time of the election, and hence that Benedict’s resignation was valid
(condition 1); that no illegal activities of the St. Gallans Mafia were
sufficient to invalidate the election (condition 2), and that Pope Francis
himself personally met all the conditions required for him to become Pope.
Another way to put it is that if Benedict had remained Pope due to
a defect in his resignation, or if any other condition for
Francis to be legitimately elected was not satisfied, God would not have
permitted his election to be accepted by the entire Church. Cardinal
Billot and John of St. Thomas both address this point directly:
John of St. Thomas: it
is not merely a pious belief, but a theological conclusion (as we have stated),
that God will not permit one to be elected and peacefully accepted by the
Church who in fact does not meet the conditions required; this
would be contrary to the special providence that God exercises over the Church
and the assistance that she receives from the Holy Ghost.
Cardinal Billot teaches
the same: the infallible providence of God will prevent it from ever
happening that the whole Church adhere to a false head; consequently, no one will
ever be accepted as supreme pontiff who does not meet all the conditions
necessary to be a member, whatever those conditions may be.
That visibility, therefore, by which the true Church is recognizable as such,
is in no way imperiled.
Smith: I would like to
know how one can speak of the “unanimous teaching of theologians”. You only
cite five. How does such a small number constitute unanimity?
Besides, excepting John of St. Thomas, all these theologians were active in
modern times; there is no real theological tradition on this point, so far
as I am aware, and without it we cannot speak of unanimity in any meaningful
sense.”
Siscoe: The reason
it can be said that the doctrine is the “unanimous teaching of the theologians”
is because it is taught in virtually all theological manuals, and the manuals
that don’t mentioned, also don’t deny it.
As we saw earlier, even the Sedes admit the doctrine is true, even
though it’s the one that gives them the most problems. I would also note that you haven’t provided
any authority who denies it, or any who support your position that it only
applies to past Popes.
Regarding the doctrine
not being rooted in Tradition. Interestingly, Bishop Gracida raised the
exact opposite objection in response to an article I wrote on this subject for
One Peter Five. He argued that the peaceful and universal acceptance is
an “outdate doctrine” from the middle ages - from a time when there was no
“printing press” (why that matters, he didn’t explain) - and then stated that
John Paul II forbade anyone to appeal to it to confirm the legitimacy of a
papal election. He conveniently ignored the fact that I quoted numerous
authorities from the 20th century (one from 1965) in the
article he was commenting on. He also
ignored the fact that recent canonists have appealed to the doctrine to prove
the legitimacy of Francis’ election. Let me provide one such quote now.
Reply to Bishops Gracida’s Objection – “the Doctrine is too Old”[4]
In November of 2015, Dr.
Boni, professor of Canon Law at the University of Bologna, and Advisor of
the Pontifical Council for Legislative Texts (by appointment of Pope
Benedict), published an article in response to Antonio Socci’s book that
questioned the legitimacy of Francis election. After addressing each
of the objections Socci raised, the esteemed canonist ended the article as
follows:
Dr. Boni: “On the contrary, even if what has
been reported had happened [i.e., if the alleged irregularities that Socci
presented were true], the procedure that followed, as I have demonstrated,
would have been entirely ‘ad normam iuris’ (as provided by law): the
election of Pope Francis, having reached the expected majority in the fifth
ballot (the first, I remember, occurred on May 12), it would be valid, there
would be nothing to heal, there would be no doubt, much less a
‘positive’ and ‘insoluble’ doubt (as the law postulates) of the validity.
“Give the complete lack of legal foundation for
these suppositions [presented by Socci], even if one wanted to give credit to
the information on which these claims are based, the rashly agitated claim of a
‘doubtful’ Pope actually seated on the chair of Peter vanishes. And
anyway the canonists have constantly taught that the
peaceful universal adhesion of the Church is a sign and infallible effect of a
valid election of a legitimate Pope: and the adhesion of the people of God
to Pope Francis cannot be placed in any doubt.”[5]
Dr. Boni followed up six
months later by publishing a scholarly study on the same subject,
titled Beyond a Resignation. The Decision of Pope Benedict XVI and The
Law (Bologna 2015), and again used the doctrine of the peaceful and
universal acceptance to prove the legitimacy of Francis election – which she
would not have done if it was an “outdated doctrine” from the Middle Ages that
John Paul II forbade anyone to appeal to confirm the legitimacy of a papal
election, as Bishop Gracid claimed.
I should also ask, since
Bishop Gracida believes the only factor in determining if a papal election is
valid, is if it meets the requirements of U.D.G (the legislation for Papal
elections promulgated by John Paul II), what will happen if Benedict and
Francis die, and the “Cardinals” appointed by Francis elect the next Pope? Will Bishop Gracida accept the legitimacy of
the one they elect, or will he reject it on the basis that the Cardinal
electors were appointed by an antipope, and hence had no legal right to elect a supreme Pontiff?
We don’t have to wonder
what the answer is, since Bishop Gracida has already provided the answer: The following demonstrates the grievous consequences of Bishop Gracida’s error:
Bishop Gracida: “Finally, it is important to
understand that the sheer number of putative counterfeit cardinals will eventually, sooner or later, result in a
situation in which The Church will have no normal means validly ever again to
elect a Vicar of Christ. After that
time, it will become even more difficult, if
not humanly impossible, for the College of Cardinals to rectify the current
disastrous situation and conduct a proper and valid Conclave[.]”
In case you didn’t
notice, this is the identical line of reasoning that the heretics of the 19th
century used to argue that the legitimate succession of Popes had ceased - an
error that the Catholics scholars of the day all refuted by appealing to the
doctrine of the peaceful and universal acceptance.
Reply to Smith’s Objection – “the Doctrine is too New”
To address your
objection I will provide an excerpt from the monumental work Prompta
Bibliotheca Canonica (1746), which the Catholic Encyclopedia refers to
as “a veritable encyclopedia of religious knowledge,” written by the
renowned Italian canonist, Lucius Ferraris.
The book was published
during the pontificate of Benedict XIV, who Farraris refers to by
name and says his legitimacy is a matter of faith. What else is
significant is that Farraris cites the decree of Martin V to prove it – that
is, to prove that the legitimacy of the currently reigning Pope
is de fide:
“It is of faith that Benedict
XIV [currently reigning Pope], for instance, legitimately elected and accepted
as such by the Church, is the true Pope—(common doctrine among Catholics). This
is proved from the Council of Constance, sess. ult. where Martin V. Const.
Inter Cunctus, decrees that those who return from heresy to the faith shall be
asked, among other points, ‘Whether they believe that the Pope canonically
elected, for the time being, his name being expressly mentioned, is
the successor of St. Peter, having supreme authority in the Church of God.’ For
thereby he supposes it to be an article of faith, since those who abjure heresy
are ‘interrogated only as to truths of faith.’ (…)
“Through the mere fact that the Church
receives him as legitimately elected, God reveals to us the legitimacy of his
election, since Christ has promised that His Church shall never err in a
matter of faith, . . . whereas she would err in such matter of faith if the
conclusion did not hold.”[6]
Referring to the
definition of Martin V, you wrote:
Smith: “What exactly does “who lived for a time” (quo tempore
fuerit) mean? Literally it means “in the time which he *was* [pope]”.
This probably is referring to former popes, excluding the present one.
Siscoe: No, it is referring to the current Pope,
which is why both Farraris and John of St. Thomas insert name of the currently
reigning Pope when they explained the teaching. Here’s is John of St. Thomas’
explanation, which leaves no doubt that he understands it as referring to the
present Pope:
“Martin V, in the
Council of Constance, in the condemnation of the errors of Wyclif, which is to
be found after the fourth, fifth, and last sessions of the Council, in the
interrogations that are to be made of those whose faith is suspect, to see
whether they rightly believe, puts this question.
‘Also, whether he
believes that the Pope canonically elected, who is reigning at the time (his
proper name being given), is the successor of Blessed Peter, having supreme
authority in the Church of God?’
“These words do not
speak of the truth of that proposition understood in a general sense—namely,
that whoever is lawfully elected is the Supreme Pontiff—but in
the particular, concerning whoever is pope at the time,
giving his proper name, for instance, Innocent X [the Pope at the time he was
writing]. It is of this man, whose proper name is given, that the pope
[Martin V] is bidding the person suspect in faith to be asked, whether he
believes that such a person is the successor of Peter and the Supreme
Pontiff: therefore this pertains to the act of faith—not to an
inference or a moral certitude; for neither of the latter two is a matter of
faith.” (Corpus, n. 13)
There is no doubt that John of St. Thomas believed the question
pertained to the currently reigning Pope. Also note that both Farris and John
of St. Thomas teach that the decree of Martin V proves that the legitimacy of
the currently reigning Pope is de fide.
As we will see in a moment, Cardinal Ratzinger, when he was head of the Congregation for the Doctrine of
Faith, taught the same in hia clarification on the 1989 Profession of
Faith. Before we get to that, let me address one final objection.
St. Alphonsus on a Doubtful Election
It was recently brought to my attention that someone named Fred
Martinez, of The Catholic Monitor, has posted numerous articles
questioning why I provided the following quotation from St. Alphonsus Ligouri, without including the last sentence, which is in bold below:
'It is of no importance
that in the past centuries some Pontiff was illegitimately elected or took
possession of the Pontificate by fraud; it is enough that he was accepted
afterward by the whole Church as Pope, since by such acceptance he would become
the true Pontiff. But if for a certain time, he was not accepted
universally and truly by the Church, during that time then, the pontifical see
would be vacant, as it is vacant at the death of a Pope.' 'Verita Della
Fede', Part III, Ch. VIII, p. 720.'"
Martinez asks: “Did Siscoe leave it out because [1] he is a poor
scholar or [2] for some other reason or [3] because it said ‘for a certain
time’? He nor I know when this ‘certain time’ is? Is that ‘certain
time’ immediately at the conclave or is it a few years after the conclave?”
Siscoe: The answer is #2: I left the last sentence off “for
some other reason,” namely, because it does not apply to the
controversy concerning the legitimacy Francis Pontificate. And it may
surprise Mr. Martinez to learn that I do indeed know what St. Alphonsus meant
by “for a certain time,” since what he is referring to is something canonists
and theologians discuss quite regularly.
The last sentence is referring to the case of a Pope whose election
is in doubt from the beginning, but who is later
accepted as Pope by the entire Church. He’s not referring to a Pope whose
election was accepted by the entire Church for over a year, before
being questioned by some, as is the case with the election of Francis.
The following quotation
from Guéranger’s, The Liturgical Year, discusses the same
situation that St. Alphonsus was referring to in the last sentence. In the following quote, Guéranger uses the
phrase “for a while,” which is essentially the same as “for a certain time”:
“The inevitable play of human passions,
interfering in the election of the Vicar of Christ, may perchance for
a while [i.e., “for a certain time”] render uncertain the
transmission of spiritual power. But when it is proved that the Church, still
holding, or once more put in possession of her liberty, acknowledges in the
person a certain Pope, until then doubtful, as the true Sovereign
Pontiff, this her very recognition is a proof that, from that moment at
least, the occupant of the Apostolic See is as such invested by God
himself.” (Abbot Guéranger, O.S.B., The Liturgical Year, Vol XII, pg. 188)
This is a common
teaching of the canonists. If a Pope is not accepted by the entire Church
from the beginning, even if he is the legitimate Pope quoad se (in
himself), no one is bound to recognize him as Pope. This is what is meant
by the axiom, “a doubtful Pope is considered no Pope at all”, which is an
application of the principle, “a doubtful law is no law at all”.
Fr. Wernz discusses this at length in Ius Decretalium (1898).[7]
Cardinal Journet
discusses the same situation in the The Church of the Word Incarnate,
and explains that when a papal election is in doubt from the beginning (immediately
contested by part of the Church) the election itself is
considered to be ongoing:
Cardinal Journet: “The Church has the right to
elect the Pope, and therefore the right to certain knowledge as to who is
elected. As long as any doubt remains and the tacit
consent of the universal Church has not yet remedied the
possible flaws in the election, there is no Pope, papa dubius, papa
nullus [‘a doubtful Pope is no Pope’]. As a matter of fact, remarks
John of St. Thomas, in so far as a peaceful and certain election is not
apparent, the election is regarded as still going on.” (Cardinal Journet, The
Church of the World Incarnate, London: Sheed and Ward, 1955, p. 481)
That is the situation St.
Alphonsus is referring to in the last sentence.
Again, the reason it was I did not include it in the article Mr.
Martinez was commenting on is because it doesn’t pertain to the election of
Francis.
Congregation for the
Doctrine of Faith
In the late 90’s, Cardinal Ratzinger, while head of the
Congregation for the Doctrine of Faith, confirmed “the unanimous teaching of the
theologians” by stating that the legitimacy of a papal election is de
fide. He did so in his clarification of the Profession of Faith that was promulgated
by John Paul II in 1989.
The Professio contains three categories of
doctrines that Catholics must accept. The first category consists of defined
dogmas (formally revealed truths) that demand the assent of divine and Catholic
faith. The second category consists of
revealed truths (material dogmas) that have been infallibly proposed (but not
infallibly proposed, as revealed), as well as non-revealed truths (secondary
objects of infallibility) that have been infallibly taught, and hence demand
the assent of faith.
Here is what Ratzinger wrote about truths contained in second
category, as well as the obligation that Catholics have of adhering to them.
“The second proposition of the Professio
fidei states: ‘I also firmly accept and hold each and
everything definitively proposed by the Church regarding teaching on faith and
morals.’
“The object taught by this formula
includes all those teachings belonging to the dogmatic or moral area,
which are necessary for faithfully keeping and expounding the deposit of faith,
even if they have not been proposed by the Magisterium of the Church as
formally revealed.
“Such doctrines can be defined solemnly by
the Roman Pontiff when he speaks 'ex cathedra' or by the College of Bishops
gathered in council, or they can be taught infallibly by the ordinary
and universal Magisterium of the Church as a ‘sententia definitive tenenda’. Every
believer, therefore, is required to give firm and definitive assent to
these truths, based on faith in the Holy Spirit's assistance to the
Church's Magisterium, and on the Catholic doctrine of the infallibility of the
Magisterium in these matters. Whoever denies these truths would be in a
position of rejecting a truth of Catholic doctrine and would therefore no
longer be in full communion with the Catholic Church.
He goes on to further clarify what doctrines are
contained in this category:
“The truths belonging to this second paragraph
can be of various natures, thus giving different qualities to their
relationship with revelation. There are truths which are necessarily connected
with revelation by virtue of an historical relationship [i.e., dogmatic facts];
while other truths evince a logical connection [i.e., theological conclusions]
that expresses a stage in the maturation of understanding of revelation which
the Church is called to undertake. (…) With regard to those truths connected to
revelation by historical necessity and which are to be held definitively, but
are not able to be declared as divinely revealed, the following examples can be
given: the legitimacy of the election of the Supreme Pontiff [.]”
Notice that.
The legitimacy of the election of the Supreme Pontiff must be accepted
with a definitive assent – i.e., the assent of faith.
This shows that it is no minor error to reject
the validity of Francis election, or treat it as a matter that can be
doubted. On the contrary, anyone who
denies the legitimacy of a Papal election that the Church herself has accepted,
which is certainly the case of Francis’ election, is “in a position of rejecting
a truth of Catholic doctrine” and is no longer “in full communion with the
Catholic Church.” Not being “in full
communion with the Catholic Church” is Vatican II speak for being cut off from
the Church – outside of which there is no salvation.
[1] I should note that many theologians today maintain that doctrines which are not formally revealed, but instead only have a connection to revealed truths, are only held with ecclesiastical faith, not divine faith. But the reason for this difference does not have any bearing on the matter at hand.
[4] https://abyssum.org/2019/03/23/why-do-intelligent-men-pursue-the-application-of-an-obsolete-concept-universal-acceptance-to-the-problem-of-the-invalidity-of-the-papacy-of-francis-the-merciful-in-this-day-and-age-of-instant-elec/
[6] Ferraris,Prompta Bibliotheca canonica.,
article Papa, p. 949; quoted in “Dr. Littledale’s Theory of the Disappearance
of the Papacy,” Catholic Truth Society, Vol. XXVI, ( London, 1895) p. 7
[7] Fr. Franz Xaver Wernz, Ius Decretalium ad
Usum Praelectionum In Scholis Textus Canonicisive Juris Decretalium, , Tomus
II, (Romae: De Propoganda Fide, 1898) Scholion 618.